7 feb 2017

Psychoanalysis and group analysis

PSYCHOANALISIS AND GROUP ANALYSIS

Towards a new paradigm of the human being *

Juan Tubert Oklander, MD, PhD **

Let us start from the beginning: psychoanalysis has shown, from its very inception, a dual nature, which has been present and generated an inner tension ever since Freud’s writings. This stemmed from a deep contradiction in his character and work. On the one hand, he was a medical man, with a solid training in anatomical and physiological research, with a staunch conviction that Science —and this necessarily meant for him the positivistic and reductionist science he had learned from his teachers— was the only valid and reliable path to knowledge (Freud, 1933a). Consequently, he consciously intended that the new discipline he had created be just another natural science, for “Psychology, too, is a natural science. What else can it be?” (1940b, p. 282).

On the other hand, he was a child of Romanticism, who loved Goethe, and had a hidden and unacknowledged penchant for intuition and what he derogatorily called “occultism” (Freud, 1922a, 1941d [1921]). This was largely repressed and frequently denied, but it emerged most clearly in his clinical practice.

But it was not only his Romantic inheritance that prevented him from becoming the stern positive scientist he strived to be. There was also a pull from the very nature of the mental processes he was studying. This he was quite aware of. In his case story of Elizabeth von R., in Studies on Hysteria (Breuer & Freud, 1895), he writes the following caveat:

I have not always been a psychotherapist. Like other neuropathologists, I was trained to employ local diagnoses and electro-prognosis, and it still strikes me myself as strange that the case histories I write should read like short stories and that, as one might say, they lack the serious stamp of science. I must console myself with the reflection that the nature of the subject is evidently responsible for this, rather than any preference of my own. [p. 160, italics added]

So he was afraid of losing “the serious stamp of science”. But why on earth did he feel the need to excuse himself for doing what he did best—namely, clinical research? Probably because he was afraid that his discoveries and ideas might be rejected by the scientific and academic Establishment he so passionately yearned to be a part of.

In any case, this contradiction in Freud’s feelings and thoughts was continued in the later development of psychoanalysis, and ever since there have been two quite disparate ways of conceiving, thinking, and practicing our discipline. One of them searches for impersonal causal explanations, just as in natural science, and views psychoanalytical practice as a purposive technical intervention, steered by a precise knowledge of well-proven facts and theories. The other sees the psychoanalytical treatment as a personal relationship and develops a highly personal theory of meaning and relations, in order to account for human experience and behavior, as well as for the most unexpected events that occur whenever two or more people meet in a closed space, during a fixed time, in order to “do analysis”.

The former approach is usually referred to as “metapsychological”, while the latter is nowadays called “relational”. Although the relational point of view may well be seen as the later development of some of Freud’s insights —as, for instance, in “Mourning and melancholia” (1917e) and “The Ego and the Id” (1923b), and a myriad clinical observations— this was at odds with his attempt to put forward a strictly scientific theory. It was Sándor Ferenczi (1955, 1985; Ferenczi and Rank, 1924) who first developed a personal psychoanalytic theory of relations and conceived psychoanalysis in terms of a shared experience —the “analytic experience”. But his contributions were foreclosed by the psychoanalytic community, as a result of Freud’s utter rejection, and only reemerged in a watered-down version fifteen years after his death, in the work of the British Object-Relations Theorists. In the US, these ideas flowered in the Interpersonal Psychoanalysis and Self Psychology traditions, which were in sharp contrast with that of the Freudian group.

In the past few decades, the Relational Psychoanalysis movement, which originated in the US but has now become an international endeavor, has created a dialogic space for the confluence of these various relational trends (and some others, derived from Lacanian, Jungian, and interpersonal analysis, and the study of early mother-child interaction)(Aron, 1996; Mitchell & Aron, 1999). It is interesting to notice that the more unorthodox aspects of this approach, particularly in matters of technique, transcend those posed by the various previous relational schools and are more akin to Ferenczi’s adventurous expansion of the limits of psychoanalytic technique recorded in his Clinical Diary of 1932, which was only published in French in 1985. When the English translation finally appeared in 1988, the initial members of the Relational group were happy to find out this long-lost ancestor and precursor of their own explorations (Aron, 1996).

There is, however, something missing in this reconstruction of the historical development of the relational perspective. What has gone unnoticed in the now vast literature on Relational Psychoanalysis is that there has been another group of analysts who have been working on similar lines since the late 1930s: the practitioners of Group Analysis. This omission is perhaps understandable, since most relational psychoanalysts work within the limits of the bipersonal therapeutic device created by Freud, and those who do work with groups, therapeutic or otherwise, do it in in terms of other conceptions of group work, informed by psychoanalytical theory and technique, which conceives clinical phenomena in either intrapersonal or interpersonal terms —this being what is usually called “analytic group psychotherapy”.

Group Analysis is a discipline that was born independently and simultaneously in two distant places: England, in the work of S. H. Foulkes (1948, 1964a), and Argentina, in that of Enrique Pichon-Rivière (1971a; Tubert-Oklander & Hernández-Tubert, 2004). It is quite different from analytic group psychotherapy, which is the application of psychoanalytical theories and techniques, derived from the bipersonal therapeutic setting, to the treatment of individuals in groups. Group analysis, on the other hand, recognizes the specific nature of group processes and approaches groups, both therapeutic and non-therapeutic, with an analytic attitude for the inquiry of whatever emerges in them, analyzing it in intrapersonal, interpersonal, and transpersonal terms. Although it makes use of psychoanalytical and psychological knowledge and theories, as well as those generated by the social sciences, it studies and analyzes its particular form of experience —the group-analytic experience— and constructs new theories from it, pretty much as psychoanalysis does with the psychoanalytic experience.

I believe that both psychoanalysis and group analysis are only aspects of the wider field of analysis, which is a new path for the inquiry and understanding of human affairs inaugurated by Sigmund Freud. He invented a specific procedure to be used for therapeutic and research purposes, which intended to focus on the study of the intrapersonal mental processes, but later had to be amplified to include interpersonal processes. Group analysis, which started from the study of therapeutic and institutional groups, created its own device for inquiry and intervention in human groups: the group-analytic group, which may be either small, median, or large.

The specificity of group analysis derives from the fact that it studies transpersonal processes. This term refers to mental processes that, although they share almost all the features of personal processes, at the intrapersonal or interpersonal level, they lack the feeling of I-ness that characterizes them. They are subjectless mental processes that surround, traverse, and largely determine the organization and dynamics of individuals and their relations with others. These include historical, cultural, social, political, institutional, and group processes. Freud had approached this concept in two of his social writings, Totem and Taboo (1912–1913) and Moses and Monotheism (1939a)—particularly in the latter, in which he studies what he had previously (1933a, p. 147) called “cultural evolution” (Hernández-Tubert, 2008, 2012).

The group-analytic perspective and theory are what we call a holistic approach. This means that their particular form of observation, analysis, and theoretical understanding of their subject matter —i.e., human affairs— is based on the assumption that systems should be viewed as wholes, and not as a collection of parts, and that the properties and behavior of the system cannot be inferred from the study of the isolated parts. This implies a serious criticism of the research strategy of positivistic science of tackling the study of any complex entity or situation by splitting it into simpler parts, studying them in detail, and then reconstructing the original whole from the summation of the now well-known properties of the parts; this we usually call the “analytic method”. Holistic thinking claims, on the contrary, that the so-called “parts” are really created by such analytical splitting (whether it is a physical split or a conceptual dissection), as an artifact of the analytic technique. In actual reality, the nature, properties and behavior of the various elements that may be identified in a complex system, can only be fully understood in terms of its global organization and functioning. This is usually summarized by the aphorism “the whole is prior to, more than, and more elementary than the sum of the parts”.

Such holistic theory is, at one and the same time, a field theory and a process theory (Tubert-Oklander 2016a, b). Field theories organize their observational data as a set of simultaneously occurring interdependent phenomena, so that, at any given time, whatever occurs in any part of the field is determined by and has an influence on all other parts of the field. Hence, anything that happens in the field can only be fully accounted for in terms of the organization and dynamics of the field at that moment (Tubert-Oklander, 2007, 2013a, 2013b).

The scope of the observation of a field is necessarily limited by the nature of the observational device applied. Therefore, the bipersonal device of psychoanalysis is especially suited for the study of intrapersonal and interpersonal processes. The group-analytic small group, on the other hand, focuses on interpersonal and group process, while large groups are especially suited for observing and analyzing intergroup and social processes in cultural, political, and organizational terms. We presently lack an observational device for the study of national and international processes, although we can use group-analytic theory to analyze them, this being applied group analysis (Tubert-Oklander & Hernández-Tubert, 2014b).

Such approach is clearly akin to what relational psychoanalysts have been trying to do in their inquiry and understanding of what happens in the analytic situation. Michael Balint pointed out, in his 1968 book The Basic Fault, the inadequacy of a one-person theory for accounting for observations made in a two-person setting (Balint, 1968–1979). John Rickman (1950, 1951) had already clearly differentiated, more than fifteen years before, the one-person, two-person, three-person, and multi-person psychologies, the latter being for him the only necessary backbone of theory for group practice (1950, p. 168).

This required the introduction of new concepts for the better understanding of bipersonal psychoanalysis, such as Madeleine and Willy Baranger’s (1961-1962, 2008, 2009) conception of the analytic field and Stephen A. Mitchell’s (1988) concept of the relational matrix. But the Barangers conceived the field as derived from the interaction between the two parties and implicitly restricted it to the confines of the analytic space and time —i.e., the office and the sessions— thus excluding the whole social dimension. Mitchell’s matrix, on the other hand, included the social and cultural dimensions, but viewed them in terms of their impact on the individual and the dyad, thus leaving out the study of transpersonal processes as such.

The analytic field —both psychoanalytic and group-analytic— cannot be fairly conceived as a product of the interaction of the participating parties, nor can it be restricted to the spatial limits of the office or the temporal limits of the sessions, or even of the whole treatment. The field extends in all directions, both spatial and temporal, until it fades into the dim horizon of our perception and awareness. Hence, what is presently happening in a session may be better understood in terms of things that are happening beyond the room and include many other people or groups —such as the various groups and institutions analyst and patient belong to, the cultures in which either or both of them were reared, or the social and political context in which both are embedded. The same applies to events that have happened long before the beginning of the treatment, or even before either party was born, or possible, anticipated, wished-for, or feared events in the near or distant future. Hence, the field cannot be thought in terms of our common-sense conception of things, nor even in its formalized version in scientific thinking, which only considers the material as “real”, but rather as an experiential field, a mental phenomenon that obeys the laws of Mind, and not those of Matter.

Therefore, the analytic field is not actually created when analyst and patient meet for the first time. In a very concrete sense, it may be said that it was already there, waiting for them to come and inhabit it. This statement is obviously related to Bion’s (1970, 1980) metaphor of “thoughts in search of a thinker”.

These ideas are implicit in the theory of the Matrix that S. H. Foulkes introduced as a basic concept of group-analytic theory. He defined the matrix as “the hypothetical web of communication and relationship in a given group. It is the common shared ground which ultimately determines the meaning and significance of all events and upon which all communications and interpretations, verbal and nonverbal, rest” (Foulkes, 1964b, p. 292).

As you can well see, this is a particular type of field theory. There is a gossamer web of connections that surrounds individuals, goes through them, and determines their inner organization, behavior, and relations. Just as his neurologist teacher and Gestalt theorist Kurt Goldstein had conceived the nervous system as a network of connections, and neurons as the focal points in that web, Foulkes viewed the group as a network of communications and relations, and the individuals as its focal points, that is, the places in which the connections intercross and coalesce. And anything that happens within that matrix is determined by its organization and dynamics.

But how is it that the matrix determines the individual? This is because the individual also has a matricial organization, but such organization is not a closed system, since it is always open and connected to both higher and lower level matrixes. So the individual matrix is embedded in and connected with the group matrix, just the latter is in the institutional and social matrix, and the field extends in all directions, even though our conscious mind cannot encompass such overwhelming complexity.

The idea of the individual as a matrix is obviously at odds with the Jacksonian hierarchical organization of the psychic apparatus posed by Freudian metapsychology. Then, why should we embark on such a radical revision of our theory? The only valid reason is that it paves the way for the inclusion a great deal of phenomena that could not be easily included in a theory that took as an axiom and starting point the existence of the isolated individual. The intrapsychic point of view, which should really be called “intrapersonal”, could manage to explain subjective experience, but was at a loss when trying to account for collective living, or even for what happens when two or more individuals meet, communicate, and interact. So, we need another approach in order to explain how people understand and influence each other, what happens when they join in groups of more than three members, and the very nature and functioning of collective entities such as groups, communities, institutions, societies, regions, nations, or the international system. And each and every one of these neglected areas has an impact on a person’s experience, motives, beliefs, values, thoughts, feelings, behavior, and relations, so that psychoanalysis can ill afford the cost of ignoring them.

Foulkes conceived the group’s dynamic matrix as something that is set in motion as a result of the members’ interaction that ensues when they meet. But this is only possible because it is based on and embedded in a deeper foundation matrix, which antedates the inception of the group. It is the field that is already there before the group members first meet.

The foundation matrix is what the analyst and the patient, or the members of a group and its conductor or conductors have in common, and which allows them to interact, communicate, and understand each other. It encompasses language, culture, nationality, and social, historical, and ethnic background. This is what we refer to as the Social Unconscious (Hopper, 2003a, b; Hopper & Weinberg, 2011, 2016, in press) but it also includes the even deeper and universal features that stem from the fact that we all belong to the same species, this being the ground covered by Freud´s drive theory and his concept of primordial fantasies, as well as Jung´s theory of the Collective Unconscious.

Now, this deep layer of experience is related to the concept of a primeval fusional experience of being at one with everything that is, which I have called the Syncretic Paradigm (Tubert-Oklander, 2014a). This idea, which derives from Romain Rolland’s “feeling of Eternity”, which Freud (1930a) called the “oceanic feeling”, has been developed in the work of Sándor Ferenczi (1924), Hans Loewald (1980), Margaret Mahler (1968), José Bleger (1967), Blanca Montevechio (1999, 2002), and myself (Tubert-Oklander, 2014a). It is not just a primitive stage of mental development, which may or may not survive in adult living, as Freud (1930a) thought, but rather a permanent phase of minding, which coexists and interacts dialectically with other, more discriminate, phases during the whole life span.

The syncretic phase of mainly unconscious experience —which I have called, following Montevechio’s use of myths, “Dionysian”— is characterized by syncretism and ambiguity. Ambiguity, a term introduced by Bleger (1967) refers to a state of complete originary non-discrimination between subject and object, inner and outer, love and hate, masculine and feminine, mind and body, self and environment; hence, it presents a confluence of opposing passions. This is the most primitive and vital stratum of mental functioning, from which all social life derives, since in it there is a primal continuity and fusion between individuals and everything that surrounds them. It is the basis of all social feelings and relations, such as empathy, solidarity, cooperation, and compassion (Bleger, 1971; Montevechio, 2002). This is a non-representational form of experience and relationship, one that is based on the emotional and bodily experiences that, unlike the subjectivity of iconic though and verbal thought, may be readily shared.

Just as the syncretic phase is represented by Dionysus, the specular and iconic phase of minding corresponds to Narcissus, and the verbal, discriminate, and rational one, to Oedipus. The three of them are in a constant dialectic interaction, which is the very essence of human existence.

All these concepts stemmed from the study of intra-personal mental processes, but they can and should be readily applied to those collective mental processes that group analysis inquires. I believe that this is the only way in which concepts such as “field” and “matrix” can be sorted out and be integrated with those that emerged from bipersonal psychoanalysis. I have recently tackled this task in a chapter for a collective book, which is presently in press, on the Social Unconscious, edited by Earl Hopper and Haim Weinberg (Tubert-Oklander, in press). There I show how the Syncretic Paradigm can be articulated with Foulkes’s (1957) descriptions of the various levels to be found in group processes, which I prefer to call “phases”, in order to avoid the verticality of a multi-level scheme, which implies that some levels are somehow superior to others. The term “phases”, on the contrary, suggests a cyclic sequence of states, like the phases of the moon, in which there cannot be any hierarchy.

Now, when I spoke of holistic theories, I said that any such theory should be, at one and the same time, a field theory and a process theory. I have dealt, quite extensively, with the field concept, but what about the process? Just as the field represents a way of organizing our data as if they were all operating simultaneously, the process view organizes its data as a sequence in time. So, we may say that field theories use a spatial model of events, and process theories recur to temporal models. A process is a sequence of changes over time, though not just any such sequence, but an organized one —i.e., an evolution with a direction and a course, and this implies an aim and determines a meaning. And the organization is not static, but dynamic, since the process steers itself towards its aim.

This view was developed by Enrique Pichon-Rivière (1971a, b; Tubert-Oklander, 2014b; Tubert-Oklander & Hernández-Tubert, 2004), the pioneer of psychoanalysis and group analysis in Argentina. He conceived psychoanalysis, both in its bipersonal and its collective forms, as a dialectical spiral process. The image of the spiral has traditionally been used to represent dialectics, since it implies a three-fold progressive movement: it has a circular displacement, since it goes back, over and over, to the same themes; then there is an expansion, since each turn does not come back exactly to the same point, but is ever widening its scope, and finally, there is a progressive evolution, which advances in space, determining a three-dimensional cone-shaped spiral.

Nonetheless, in Pichon-Riviere’s thought, the spiral is not only a dialogue, framed in verbal terms, but also an evolution of the emotional aspects of the relations between the parties, and of their mutual interaction. Thus he approaches the Golden Braid of thought, emotion, and action (Tubert-Oklander, 2013a).

As I have already pointed out, field and process are two ways of organizing our thinking about our experiences. They are, consequently, complementary, since each of them clearly depicts some aspect of the whole, while leaving out or deficiently portraying others. Field theories are good at representing the mutual influences of the various components of a given situation but, being atemporal, they are at a loss when having to account for movement and change. On the other hand, process theories clearly depict changes in time but, being focused on their evolution, lose sight of the various components involved (Tubert-Oklander, 2016b.

Of course, I do not wish to imply that field theorists are oblivious of the temporal perspective, or that process theorists ignore the structural aspect of the persons or other elements implied in the process. Indeed they all strive to include those dimensions that are left out or poorly represented in their theory, as a result of their theory-building strategy. For instance, field theorists emphasize that the field is a dynamic one —i.e., that it changes and evolves over time— and Foulkes’s conception of the matrix is not of a permanent structure, but of a living network of connections. What I am emphasizing is that the very construction of a field view does not allow us to represent motion and change, and that this must be added as an afterthought. The same applies to a process view, which clearly shows changes in time, but is much more limited in representing the various elements and their interaction, thus forcing the process theorist to engage in minute dissections of the interactions among the parties or elements.

We may then say that a field view is like a snapshot, while a process view is like a film. Snapshots can only represent movement by means of a series of still images, as in Zeno’s arrow paradox, which reduces movement to an infinite series of still states. Films allow us to have a direct perception of movement and evolution, but they lose sight of the details in the image, and if we try to study them photogram by photogram, we will most probably find out that each individual image is much less detailed than a true still photograph. Hence, the experience of a process may be compared to Heraclitus’s river, which is never the same, and to his paradox that we can never bathe twice in the same river. Gregory Bateson (Bateson & Goleman, 1978) once paraphrased this, with his typical English humor, as “You can never go to bed twice with the same girl for the first time.”

Consequently, what we need, in order to attain a fuller description of our analytic experiences, is to oscillate between the field view and the process view, in order to attain a binocular vision, which, as we all know, adds the dimension of depth to the bidimensional monocular vision (Bateson, 1979). Much in the same way, we have to oscillate between an individual and an interpersonal perception, and between them both and a collective one, which is transpersonal —i.e., group, inter-group, institutional, communitarian, social, or political.

And this brings us to my subtitle for today’s presentation: “Towards a new paradigm of the human being”. To speak of a new paradigm is a very serious matter. Nowadays, ever since Thomas S. Kuhn (1962) introduced the concept in his The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, every major theorist or would-be theorist in psychoanalysis has claimed or suggested that his theory represents a new paradigm. Unfortunately for them, this has not been the case: the Freudian paradigm is still very much alive. What can be argued, as I did at the beginning of this presentation, is that Freud’s work is torn between two contrasting paradigms, and that this has been the source of many contradictions and the origin of separate and conflicting schools of psychoanalytic thought and practice. Actually, I do not claim to have introduced a new paradigm, but shown the urgent need for us to develop a new one (Hernández-Tubert, 2011b).

Freud’s purposive construction of theory started from the unexamined assumption, which became one of its axioms, that only the isolated individual is “real”, and that collective entities are just a collection of such individuals. This derives from the idea of an autonomous subject of thought, introduced by Descartes, which, even if it was undermined by Freud’s discovery of the unconscious, still lurks in everyday thinking and in our concept of the ego. It is also based on the materialistic metaphysics of ordinary scientific thought, which only accepts matter and energy as “real”, as it can clearly be seen in his early attempt to put forward a general theory of mind, in his 1895 Project (Freud, 1950a).

If one is convinced that the real stuff of the human being is to be found in the material basis provided by the body, then the mind becomes only an epiphenomenon of brain function and psychoanalysis should perforce be submitted to the authority of neurosciences, as Freud actually believed, albeit he never acted accordingly. This also implies that collective entities, such as groups, families, communities, institutions, societies, countries, regions, or supranational organizations are “nothing but” aggregates of individuals and that any attempt to view them as real entities is nothing but the figment of a wishful fantasy. Sociology is then reduced to psychology, just as psychology is reduced to biology, and this reduced to physics, according to the reductionist view of science Freud received from his teachers.

On the other hand, if we are convinced that the human being is primarily social and relational, and that relations, organization, and mind are as real as material objects, then we may study such entities in themselves, in terms of an enlarged ontology that is not reduced to a materialistic metaphysics. Consequently we will be studying collective structures and processes in their own terms.

But here we are faced with a new problem. If we take as a starting point the assumption of the existence of the isolated individual, we shall be able to explore the inner workings of a person, but not to account for the obvious fact that human beings communicate and relate to each other. In other words, having installed a chasm between human beings, we will be at odds when attempting to build bridges over the void that separates them. On the other hand, if we start from the assumption that human beings are primarily and essentially social and relational, and that in our heart of hearts we are in communion, not only with other people, but also with all of Humanity, Nature, and everything that is, then we will find it really difficult to account for the equally obvious fact that we human beings have a most private area of experience that cannot be fully shared with others and conceive and perceive themselves as a locus of feeling, thought, and action. In other words, how on earth does individual subjectivity emerge from communality? For a strict relational conception, the human subject is the real enigma.

Just as field and process, the individual and the group are mental constructions of the secondary process, which, unlike the primary process, is bound to abide by the rule of the excluded middle (Hernández-Tubert, 2000, 2015). S. H. Foulkes dealt with this problem in the following terms:

To us intra-psychic does not convey … “intradermic”, and we look upon the dynamic processes in the group not from the outside, but from inside, as intra-psychic dynamics in their interaction (Foulkes & Anthony, 1957–1965, p. 21).

Both aspects, the individual and the social one, are not only integrated in our approach, but their artificial isolation —never found in actual reality— does not arise (Foulkes, 1961, p. 148).

Each individual —itself an artificial, though plausible, abstraction— is basically and centrally determined, inevitably, by the world in which he lives, by the community, the group, of which he forms a part (1948, p. 10).

In the same vein, Enrique Pichon-Rivière wrote:

The bond, which is originally external, then becomes internal, and then external again, and afterwards it becomes internal again, and so on, thus permanently taking the shape of this dialectic spiral, this passage of what is inside to the outside, and what is outside to the inside, which contributes to establish the notion of the limits between the inside and the outside (Pichon-Rivière, 1979, p. 55, my translation, italics added).

So, there is no opposition, for either of them, between the individual and society, since they form an indissoluble unit, a dynamic field. To quote Pichon Rivière again, he says:

One cannot think in terms of a distinction between the individual and society. It is an abstraction, a reductionism that we cannot accept, because we carry society within us (p. 57). [And also] The psychological field is the field of the interactions between the individual and the environment. This is why we may say that the very object of psychology is the interaction field. … This is precisely where we are working, in the place in which there used to be a dichotomy between the individual and society (p. 61, italics added).

It could be said that both the individual and the group are illusions, but I would rather say that they are alternative constructions of human experience, and that, in order to attain a fuller grasp of our conscious and unconscious experience of life, we need to oscillate between them. Apparently, binocular vision is the name of the game, when dealing with such dire complexity.

But transcending these dilemmatic oppositions is not just an academic matter, since they bring about most distressing consequences for human life. Our Western culture has espoused, since the emergence of the bourgeoisie and the later development of Capitalism, a view of human existence based on the individual, and a conception of life as an endless competition, in which, in order to be a winner, there have to be many losers. These has been distilled and refined by our present-day Neoliberalism, also known as Late Capitalism, which magnified to the utmost degree the idea that life is a ruthless battle, and decried and demeaned the traditional virtues of cooperation, empathy, compassion, solidarity, and charity, all of them based on a communitarian paradigm. This seems to be a blind alley for Humankind, so that transcending it may well be of the utmost urgency for our very survival (Hernández Hernández, 2010; Hernández-Tubert, 2011a, b).

Nonetheless, the answer is not to be found in Collectivism. Marxism was born, just as psychoanalysis, in the same cradle of the Industrial Revolution, which had only two idols: Profit and the Machine. It was only natural for Marx and Freud to adhere to a mechanistic theory of determination, which conceived everything, from the individual, through society, to the Universe itself, as a highly complex piece of machinery. This generated another false opposition, between scientific determinism and free will. Freud’s metapsychology was deterministic and mechanistic, but the therapeutic practice he created could only make sense if a person could somehow transcend his determinations and attain a certain degree of freedom of thought and choice. This was just another of his contradictions.

In the same vein, Marx had a humanistic thought and values, but developed a rigidly deterministic theory that conceived individuals as mere pawns of the so-called “social forces”. Consequently, the social collectivistic practice that was based on his theory forcibly sacrificed the individual to collective interests and considered the human subject to be a bourgeois fallacy. It is true that, on many occasions, individuals can sacrifice themselves for the welfare of many, but this has to be their choice, and not the result of coercion, manipulation, conditioning, or deceit. Collectivism is not the same as Communitarianism.

Hence, we sorely need a new paradigm of human existence that transcends these rigid oppositions between contrasting world views. Even though the world is pretty despairing sight nowadays, in terms of the increase of hate, discrimination, greed, ruthlessness, and contempt, there are signs that something is brewing in the mental pot of human thought. Many voices, from Aristotle and Jesus of Nazareth, all the way to some of our leading thinkers, such as Umberto Eco, Leonardo Boff, Hans Küng, Martin Buber, José Saramago, and others, have called for a communitarian view of existence. Many of them are the fruit of that living humanistic practice inaugurated by Freud. It is our task to join our special contribution to many others, coming from the social sciences, the humanities, education, religion, spirituality, politics, the helping professions, philosophy, the arts, and even natural science, in order to fulfil the construction of this new paradigm of the human being, one that gives their due to the various opposing faces of human existence: the individual and the community, internal and external, determinism and free will, reason and passion, imagination and rigor, reflection and action, efficiency and understanding, identity and difference. This quest for finding a fair and balanced third position is what we call analogy, which in Greek meant “proportion”, and attaining it requires a good provision of the Aristotelean virtue of Phronesis, which is usually translated as “prudence” (Beuchot, 1997, 2003; Tubert-Oklander y Beuchot Puente, 2008).

References

Aron, L. (1996). A Meeting of Minds: Mutuality in Psychoanalysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.
Baranger, M. & Baranger, W. (1961–1962). La situación analítica como campo dinámico. Revista Uruguaya de Psicoanálisis, 4 (1): 3–54. [English translation: The analytic situation as a dynamic field. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 2008, 89: 795–826.]
Baranger, M. & Baranger, W. (2008). The analytic situation as a dynamic field. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 89: 795–826.
Baranger, M. & Baranger, W. (2009). The Work of Confluence: Listening and Interpreting in the Psychoanalytic Field, L. Glocer Fiorini (Ed.). London: Karnac.
Bateson, G. (1979). Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unit. New York, NY: Bantam.
Bateson, G. & Goleman, D. (1978). Breaking out of the double bind. Psychology Today, August 1978, 12 (3): 42–51.
Bion, W. R. (1970): Attention and Interpretation: A Scientific Approach to Insight in Psycho-Analysis and Groups. London: Tavistock.
Bion, W. R. (1980). Bion in New York and São Paulo, F. Bion (Ed.). Pertshire: Clunie.
Bleger, J. (1967). Simbiosis y ambigüedad. Estudio psicoanalítico [Symbiosis and ambiguity: A psychoanalytic study]. Buenos Aires: Paidós. [Enblish translation: Symbiosis and Ambiguity. London & New York: Routledge, 2013.]
Bleger, J. (1971b). El grupo como institución y el grupo en las instituciones [The group as an institution and the group in institutions]. In Temas de psicología.(Entrevista y grupos) [Themes in Psychology. (Interview and Groups)] (pp. 87–104). Buenos Aires: Nueva Visión.
Breuer, J. & Freud, S. (1895). Studies on Hysteria. S.E. 2.
Ferenczi, S. (1924). Thalassa: A Theory of Genitality, H. A. Bunker (Trans.). London: Karnac, 1989. [Original English publication, Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 1938, translated from Thalassa. Versuch einer Genitaltheorie, Leipzig and Vienna: Internationaler Psychoanalytischer Verlag.]
Ferenczi, S. (1955). Final Contributions to the Problems and Methods of Psycho-Analysis. New York, NY: Brunner/Mazel, 1980. [Original publication, New York, NY: Basic Books. Reprinted, London: Karnac, 2011.]
Ferenczi, S. (1985). The Clinical Diary of Sándor Ferenczi, J. Dupont (Ed.), M. Balint and N. Z. Jackson (Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard, 1988. [Originally published in French as Journal Clinique (janvier–octobre 1932), Paris: Payot.]
Ferenczi, S. and Rank. O. (1924). The Development of Psychoanalysis, C. Newton (Trad.). Madison, WI: International Universities Press, 1986. [First English publication: New York, NY: Nervous and Mental Disease. Translation of Entwicklungsziele Der Psychoanalyse, Vienna.]
Foulkes, S. H. (1948). Introduction to Group-Analytic Psychotherapy: Studies in the Social Interaction of Individuals and Groups. London: Karnac, 1984. [Original publication, London: Heinemann.]
Foulkes S. H. (1957). Psychodynamic processes in the light of psychoanalysis and group analysis. In Therapeutic Group Analysis (1964a), (pp. 108–119).
Foulkes, S. H. (1961). The position of group analysis today, with special reference to the role of the Group-Analytic Society (London). In Foulkes (1990), pp. 145–150.
Foulkes, S. H. (1964a). Therapeutic Group Analysis. London: Karnac, 1984. [Original publication, London: Allen & Unwin.]
Foulkes, S. H. (1964b). A brief guide to group-analytic theory and practice. In Foulkes (1964a), pp. 281–298.
Foulkes, S. H. & Anthony, E. J. (1957–1965). Group Psychotherapy: The Psychoanalytic Approach, second edition. London: Karnac, 1984. [Original publication, London: Penguin.]
Freud, S. (1912–1913). Totem and Taboo.  S.E., 13: vii–162. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1917e). Mourning and melancholia. S.E., 14: 237–258. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1922a). Dreams and telepathy. S:E:, 18: 195–220. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1923b). The Ego and the Id. S.E. 19 1–66. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1930a). Civilization and its Discontents. S.E., 21: 64–145. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1933a). New Introductory Lectures to Psycho-Analysis, S.E., 22: 1–182. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1939a). Moses and Monotheism. S.E., 23: 1–138. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1940a). An outline of psycho-analysis. S.E. 23: 139–208. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S., (1940b). Some elementary lessons in psycho-analysis. S.E. 23: 279–286. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S., 1941d [1921]). Psycho-analysis and telepathy. S:E:, 18: 173–194. London: Hogarth.
Freud, S. (1950a). Project for a scientific psychology. S.E., 1: 281–391. London: Hogarth. [Written in 1885.]
Hernández Hernández, R. (2010). Inconsciente y concepción del mundo [The unconscious and the Weltanschauung]. Unpublished Doctor in Psychotherapy dissertation, Centre for Graduate Studies, Mexican Psychoanalytic Association, Mexico City.
Hernández de Tubert, R. (2008). El principio de exclusión en el desarrollo del movimiento psicoanalítico.’ [‘The principle of exclusion in the development of the psychoanalytic movement.’] Read at the 8th International Meeting of the International Association for the History of Psychoanalysis. Versailles, France, July 2000.
Hernández de Tubert, R. (2008). La antropología freudiana y la metasociología [Freudian anthropology and metasociology]. Revista de Psicoanálisis, 65: 29–56.
Hernández-Tubert, R. (2011a). The politics of despair: From despair to dialogue and hope. Group Analysis, 44: 27–39.
Hernández-Tubert, R. (2011b). Hacia un nuevo paradigma del ser humano: la confluencia del psicoanálisis y la hermenéutica analógica [Towards a new paradigm of the human being: Confluence of psychoanalysis and analogical hermeneutics]. Read at the 47th Congress of the International Psychoanalytical Association. Mexico City, August.
Hernández-Tubert, R. (2012). Commentary to Erik Smadja’s paper, ‘The notion of Kulturarbeit (the work of culture) in Freud’s writings. Read in a Scientific Meeting of the Mexican Psychoanalytic Association, Mexico City, February.
Hernández-Tubert (2015). Inclusion and exclusion in psychoanalysis: From splitting to integration in our theory and practice. Canadian Journal of Psychoanalysis, 23 (1):179–186
Hopper, E. (2003a). The Social Unconscious. London: Jessica Kingsley.
Hopper, E. (2003b). Traumatic Experience in the Unconscious Life of Groups. London: Jessica Kingsley.
Hopper, E. & Weinberg, H. (eds.) (2011). The Social Unconscious in Persons, Groups and Societies—Volume I: Mainly Theory. London: Karnac.
Hopper, E. & Weinberg, H. (eds.) (2016). The Social Unconscious in Persons, Groups and Societies—Volume II. London: Karnac.
Hopper, E. & Weinberg, H. (eds.) (in press). The Social Unconscious in Persons, Groups and Societies—Volume III. London: Karnac.
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago. [Reprinted, fourth edition, 2012.]
Loewald, H. W. (1980). Papers on psychoanalysis. New Haven, CT: Yale.
Mahler, M. S. (1968). On Human Symbiosis and the Vicissitudes of Individuation. Vol. I: Infantile Psychosis. New York, NY: International Universities Press.
Mitchell, S. A. (1988). Relational Concepts in Psychoanalysis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
Mitchell, S. A. & Aron, L. (Eds.) (1999). Relational Psychoanalysis: The Emergence of a Tradition. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.
Montevechio, B. (1999). Las nuevas fronteras del psicoanálisis. Dionisio, Narciso, Edipo [The new frontiers of psychoanalysis: Dionysus, Narcissus, Oedipus]. Buenos Aires: Lumen.
Montevechio, B. (2002). Más allá de Narciso. La problemática de las identidades [Beyond Narcissus: The problematic of identities]. Buenos Aires: Lumen.
Pichon-Rivière, E. (1971a). El proceso grupal. Del psicoanálisis a la psicología social (I) [The group process: From psychoanalysis to social psychology (I)]. Buenos Aires: Nueva Visión.
Pichon-Rivière, E. (1971b). La psiquiatría, una nueva problemática. Del psicoanálisis a la psicología social (II) [A new problematic for psychiatry: From psychoanalysis to social psychology (II)]. Buenos Aires: Nueva Visión.
Pichon-Rivière, E. (1979). Teoría del vínculo [Theory of the bond]. Buenos Aires: Nueva Visión.
Rickman, J. (1950). The factor of number in individual and group dynamics. In Selected Contributions to Psycho-Analysis, London: Hogarth, pp. 165–169.
Rickman, J. (1951). Number and the human sciences. In Selected Contributions to Psycho-Analysis, London: Hogarth, pp. 218–223
Tubert-Oklander, J. (2007). The whole and the parts: Working in the analytic field. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 17 (1): 115-132.
Tubert-Oklander, J. (2013a). Theory of Psychoanalytical Practice: A Relational Process Approach. London: Karnac.
Tubert-Oklander, (2013b). Field, process, and metaphor. Psychoanalytic Inquiry, 33: 229–246.
Tubert-Oklander, J. (2014a). The One and the Many: Relational Psychoanalysis and Group Analysis. London: Karnac.
Tubert-Oklander J., (2014b). Proceso en espiral (espiral dialéctica) [Spiral process (dialectic spiral). Enrique Pichon-Rivière], in Diccionario de Psicoanálisis Argentino [Dictionary of Argentine Psychoanalysis], C. L. Borensztejn, ed. Buenos Aires, Asociación Psicoanalítica Argentina.
Tubert-Oklander, J. (2016a). Why a blog on field theory? Field Theory Blog, January 10, 2016, International Field Theory Association,
Tubert-Oklander, J. (2016b) Field Theories and Process Theories. In Katz, M.; Cassorla, R. & Civitarese, G. (eds.), Advances in Contemporary Psychoanalytic Field Theory: Concept and Future Development. London & New York: Routledge.
Tubert-Oklander, J. (in press). The inner organisation of the matrix. In Hopper, E. & Weinberg, H. (eds.), The Social Unconscious in Persons, Groups and Societies—Volume III. London: Karnac.
Tubert-Oklander, J. & Beuchot Puente, M. (2008). Ciencia mestiza. Psicoanálisis y hermenéutica analógica [Hybrid science: Psychoanalysis and analogical hermeneutics]. Mexico City: Torres.
Tubert-Oklander, J. & Hernández de Tubert, R (2004). Operative Groups: The Latin-American Approach to Group Analysis. London: Jessica Kingsley.
Tubert-Oklander, J. & Hernández-Tubert, R. (2014). The social unconscious and the large group — Part II: A context that becomes text. Group Analysis, 47 (3): 329–344.




*     Read at the Psychoanalytic Institute of Northern California, San Francisco, January 3, 2017.
**    Psychoanalyst and Group Analyst. Full Member of the Mexican Psychoanalytic Association and Argentine Psychoanalytic Association, Honorary Member of the Group-Analytic Society International, Founding Member of the International Field Theory Association, and Member of the International Association of Relational Psychoanalysis and Psychotherapy.
      Email: jtubertoklander@gmail.com

2 comentarios:

  1. The best free slots casino site in the UK for 2021
    The best free slots casino site in the UK for 2021. We have over 250 games from the leading software developers in the industry luckyclub.live such as Jackpot City,

    ResponderEliminar
  2. Casino in Michigan - drmcd
    Get 정읍 출장샵 the best deals on 여수 출장샵 popular casino games at the best Michigan casino! We have top-rated games 제주도 출장마사지 from the largest video game and 군산 출장샵 live dealer  Rating: 포천 출장안마 4.1 · ‎2 reviews

    ResponderEliminar